Friday, March 29, 2013

狄拉克在此基礎上做了進一步推導[55][56],他將一個電荷和電磁場的交互作用處理為引起光子能級躍遷的微擾,能級躍遷造成了光子數量的變化,但總體上系統滿足能量和動量守恆。狄拉克成功地從第一性原理導出了愛因斯坦係數A_{ij}\,和B_{ij}\,的形式,並證明了光子的玻色-愛因斯坦統計是電磁場量子化的自然結果(玻色的推導過程正好相反,他在假設玻色-愛因斯坦統計成立的條件下導出了普朗克公式)。在狄拉克的時代,人們還不知道包括光子之內的所有玻色子都服從玻色-愛因斯坦統計。

狄拉克在此基礎上做了進一步推導[55][56],他將一個電荷和電磁場的交互作用處理為引起光子能級躍遷微擾,能級躍遷造成了光子數量的變化,但總體上系統滿足能量和動量守恆。狄拉克成功地從第一性原理導出了愛因斯坦係數A_{ij}\,B_{ij}\,的形式,並證明了光子的玻色-愛因斯坦統計是電磁場量子化的自然結果(玻色的推導過程正好相反,他在假設玻色-愛因斯坦統計成立的條件下導出了普朗克公式)。在狄拉克的時代,人們還不知道包括光子之內的所有玻色子都服從玻色-愛因斯坦統計。
狄拉克的二階微擾理論會涉及到虛光子,虛光子可以認為是極短暫的電磁場的中間態,如靜電場或靜磁場中的交互作用就是由虛光子來傳遞。

http://www.phy.ntnu.edu.tw/demolab/phpBB/viewtopic.php?topic=25005

http://mathpages.com/rr/s1-09/1-09.htm


1.9  Null Coordinates
 
Slight not what’s near through aiming at what’s far.                                                                                  Euripides, 455 BC
 
Initially the special theory of relativity was regarded by many as just a particularly simple and elegant interpretation of Lorentz's ether theory, but it gradually became clear that there is a profound difference between the two theories, most evident when we consider the singularity implicit in the Lorentz transformation x' = g(x-vt), t' = g(t-vx), where g = 1/(1-v2)1/2. As v approaches arbitrarily close to 1, the factor g goes to infinity. If these relations are strictly valid (locally), as all our observations and experiements suggest, then according to Lorentz's view all configurations of objects moving through the absolute ether must be capable of infinite spatial "contractions" and temporal "dilations", without the slightest distortion. This is inconsistent with a substantial ether, so a Lorentzian must believe that the Lorentz transformation equations are not strictly valid, i.e., that they break down at some point. Indeed, Lorentz himself argued that his view was preferable precisely because absolute speed might eventually be found to make some difference to the intrinsic relations between physical entities. However, one hundred years after Lorentz's time, there still is no sign of any such difference. To the contrary, all tests of Lorentz invariance have consistently confirmed it's exact validity. At some point we must ask ourselves "What if the Lorentz transformation really is exactly correct?" This is a possibility that a neo-etherist cannot accommodate. The Lorentzian approach is analogous to trying to define a continuous map from the surface of a sphere to a flat plane. The two surfaces have different topologies, and although stereographic projection can provide a nearly complete mapping, we need the “point at infinity” to map the “north pole” of the sphere. This shows that the surface of a sphere is the more natural representation of the topology. Likewise the null intervals of special relativity signal that the topology of spacetime is actually the one induced by the Minkowski interval, rather than supposing a contorted version of the Euclidean topology of Lorentz’s ether. (Section 9 discusses the implications of this relativistic topology for our ideas of causality.) It is also worth recalling from the previous section that the necessary and sufficient condition for Maxwell’s equations to be invariant under a given transformation is that the null intervals are preserved.
 
The singularity of the Lorentz transformation is most clearly expressed in terms of the underlying Minkowski pseudo-metric. Recall that the invariant space time interval dt between the events (t,x) and (t+dt, x+dx) is given by
 
 
where t and x are any set of inertial coordinates. This is called a pseudo-metric rather than a metric because, unlike a true metric, it doesn't satisfy the triangle inequality, and the interval between distinct points can be zero. This occurs for any interval such that dt = dx, in which case the invariant interval dt is literally zero. It’s worth noting that quantum field theory is possible only in the context of Minkowski spacetime, with its null connections between distinct events, as discussed in Section 9.10.
 
Pictorially, the locus of points whose squared distance from the origin is ±1 consists of the two hyperbolas labeled +1 and -1 in the figure below.
 
 
The diagonal axes denoted by a and b represent the paths of light through the origin, and the magnitude of the squared spacetime interval along these axes is 0, i.e., the metric is degenerate along those lines. This is all expressed in terms of conventional space and time coordinates, but it's also possible to define the spacetime separations between events in terms of null coordinates along the light-line axes. Conceptually, we rotate the above figure by 45 degrees, and regard the a and b lines as our coordinate axes, as shown below:
 
 
In terms of a linear parameterization (a,b) of these "null coordinates" the locus of points at a squared "distance" (dt)2 from the origin is an orthogonal hyperbola satisfying the equation
 
 
Since the light-lines a and b are degenerate, in the sense that the absolute spacetime intervals along those lines vanish, the absolute velocity of a worldline, given by the "slope" db/da = 0/0, is strictly undefined. This indeterminacy, arising from the singular null intervals in spacetime, is at the heart of special relativity, allowing for infinitely many different scalings of the light-line coordinates. In particular, it is natural to define the rest frame coordinates a,b of any worldline in such a way that da/db = 1. This expresses the principle of relativity, and also entails Einstein's second principle, i.e., that the (local) velocity of light with respect to the natural measures of space and time for any worldline is unity. The relationship between the natural null coordinates of any two worldlines is then expressed by the requirement that, for any given interval dt, the components da,db with respect to one frame are related to the components da',db' with respect to another frame according to the equation (da)(db) = (da')(db'). It follows that the scale factors of any two frames Si and Sj are related according to
 
 
where vij is the usual velocity parameter (in units such that c = 1) of the origin of Sj with respect to Si. Notice there is no absolute constraint on the scaling of the a and b axes, there is only a relative constraint, so the "gage" of the light-lines really is indeterminate. Also, the scale factors are simply the relativistic Doppler shifts for approaching and receding sources (see Section 2.4). This accords with the view of the ab coordinate "grid lines" as the network of light-lines emitted by a strobed source moving along the reference world-line.
 
To illustrate how we can operate with these null coordinate scale relations, let us derive the addition rule for velocities. Given three co-linear unaccelerated particles with the pairwise relative velocity parameters v12, v23, and v13, we can solve the "a scale" relation for v13 to give
 
 
We also have
 
Multiplying these together gives an expression for da1/da3, which can be substituted into (1) to give the expected result
 
 
Interestingly, although neither the velocity parameter v nor the quantity (1+v)/(1-v) is additive, it's easy to see that the parameter ln[(1+v)/(1-v)] is additive. In fact, this parameter corresponds to the arc length of the "dt = constant" hyperbola connecting the two world lines at unit distances from their intersection, as shown by integrating the differential distance along that curve
 
 
Since the equation of the hyperbola for dt = 1 is 1 = dt2 - dx2 we have
 
 
Substituting this into the previous expression and performing the integration gives
 
 
Recalling that dt2 = dt2 - dx2, we have dt + dx = dt2 / (dt - dx), so the quantity dx + dt can be written as
 
 
Hence the absolute arc length along the dt = 1 surface between two world lines that intersect at the origin with a mutual velocity v is
 
 
Naturally the additivity of this logarithmic form implies that the argument is a multiplicative measure of mutual speeds. The absolute interval between the intersection points of the two worldlines with the dt = 1 hyperbola is
 
 
One strength of the conventional pseudo-metrical formalism is that (t,x) coordinates easily generalize to (t,x,y,z) coordinates, and the invariant interval generalizes to
 
 
The generalization of the null (lightlike) coordinates and corresponding invariant is not as algebraically straightforward, but it conveys some interesting aspects of the spacetime structure. Intuitively, an observer can conceive of the absolute interval between himself and some distant future event P by first establishing a scale of radial measure outward on his forward light cone in all directions, and then for each direction evaluate the parameterized null measure along the light cone to the point of intersection with the backward null cone of P. This will assign, to each direction in space, a parameterized distance from the observer to the backward light cone of P, and there will be (in flat spacetime) two distinguished directions, along which the null measure is maximum or minimum. These are the principle directions for the interval from the observer to E, and the product of the null measures in these directions is invariant. In other words, if a second observer, momentarily coincident with the first but with some relative velocity, determines the null measures along the principle directions to the backward light cone of E, with respect to his own natural parameterization, the product will be the same as found by the first observer.
 
It's often convenient to take the interval to the point P as the time axis of inertial coordinates t,x,y,z, so the eigenvectors of the null cone intersections become singular, and we can simply define the null coordinates u = t + r, v = t - r, where r = (x2+y2+z2)1/2. From this we have t = (u+r)/2 and r = (u-v)/2 along with the corresponding differentials dt = (du+dv)/2 and dr = (du-dv)/2. Making these substitutions into the usual Minkowski metric in terms of polar coordinates
 
 
we have the Minkowski line element in terms of angles and null coordinates
 
 
These coordinates are often useful, but we can establish a more generic system of null coordinates in 3+1 dimensional spacetime by arbitrarily choosing four non-parallel directions in space from an observer at O, and then the coordinates of any timelike separated event are expressed as the four null measures radially in those directions along the forward null cone of O to the backward null cone of P. This provides enough information to fully specify the interval OP.
 
In terms of the usual orthogonal spacetime coordinates, we specify the coordinates (T,X,Y,Z) of event P relative to the observer O at the origin in terms of the coordinates of four events I1, I2, I3, I4 on the intersection of the forward null cone of O and the backward null cone of P. If ti,xi,yi,zi denote the conventional coordinates of Ii, then we have
 
 
for i = 1, 2, 3, 4. Expanding the right hand equations and canceling based on the left hand equalities, we have the system of equations
 
 
The left hand side of all four of these equations is the invariant squared proper time interval t2 from O to P, and we wish to express this in terms of just the four null measures in the four chosen directions. For a specified set of directions in space, this information can be conveyed by the four values t1, t2, t3, and t4, since the magnitudes of the spatial components are determined by the directions of the axes and the magnitude of the corresponding t. In general we can define the direction coefficients aij such that
 
 
with the condition ai12 + ai22 + ai32 = 1. Making these substitutions, the system of equations can be written in matrix form as
 
 
We can use any four directions for which the determinant of the coefficient matrix does not vanish. One natural choice is to use the vertices of a tetrahedron inscribed in a unit sphere, so that the four directions are perfectly symmetrical. We can take as the coordinates of the vertices
 
 
Inserting these values for the direction coefficients aij, we can solve the matrix equation for T, X, Y, and Z to give
 
 
 
Substituting into the relation t2 = T2 - X2 - Y2 - Z2 and solving for t2 gives
 
 
Naturally if t1 = t2 = t3 = t4 = t, then this gives t = ±2t. Also, notice that, as expected, this expression is perfectly symmetrical in the four lightlike coordinates. It's interesting that if the right hand term was absent, then t would be simply the harmonic mean of the ti.
 
More generally, in a spacetime of 1 + (D-1) dimensions, the invariant interval in terms of D perfectly symmetrical null measures t1, t2,..., tD satisfies the equation
 
 
It can be verified that with D = 2 this expression reduces to t2 = 4t1t2 , which agrees with our earlier hyperbolic formulation t2 = ab with a = 2t1 and b=2t2. In the particular case D = 4, if we define U = 2/t and uj = 1/(2tj) this equation can be written in the form
 
 
where s is the average squared difference of the individual u terms from the average, i.e.,
 
 
This is the statistical variance of the uj values. Incidentally, we've seen that the usual representation s2 = x2 - t2 of the invariant spacetime interval is a generalization of the familiar Pythagorean "sum-of-squares" equation of a circle, whereas the interval can also be expressed in the hyperbolic form s2 = ab. This reminds us of other fundamental relations of physics that have found expression as hyperbolic relations, such as the uncertainty relations
 
 
in quantum mechanics, where h is Planck's constant. In general if the operators A,B corresponding to two observables do not commute (i.e., if AB - BA ¹ 0), then an uncertainty relation applies to those two observables, and they are said to be incompatible. Spatial position and momentum are maximally incompatible, as are energy and time. Such pairs of variables are called conjugates. This naturally raises the question of whether the variables parameterizing two oppositely directed null rays in spacetime can, in some sense, be regarded as conjugates, accounting for the invariance of their product. Indeed the special theory of relativity can be interpreted in terms of a fundamental limitation on our ability to make measurements, just as can the theory of quantum mechanics. In quantum mechanics we say that it's not possible to simultaneously measure the values of two conjugate variables such that the product of the uncertainties of those two measurements is less than h/4p. Likewise in special relativity we could say that it's not possible to measure the time difference dt between two events separated by the spatial distance dx such the ratio dt/dx of the variables is less than 1/c. In quantum mechanics we may imagine that the particle possesses a precise position and momentum, even though we are unable to determine it due to practical limitations of our measurement techniques. If only we have infinitely weak signal, i.e., if only h = 0, we could measure things with infinite precision. Likewise in special relativity we may imagine that there is an absolute and precise relationship between the times of two distant events, but we are prevented from determining it due to the practical limitations. If only we had an infinnitely fast signal, i.e., if only 1/c was zero, we could measure things with infinite precision. In other words, nature possesses structure and information that is inaccessible to us (hidden variables), due to the limitations of our measuring capabilities.
 
However, it's also possible to regard the limitations imposed by quantum mechanics (h ¹ 0) and special relativity (1/c ¹ 0) not as limitations of measurement, but as expressions of an actual ambiguity and "incompatibility" in the independent meanings of those variables. Einstein's central contribution to modern relativity was the idea that there is no one "true" simultaneity between spatially separate events, but rather spacetime events are only partially ordered, and the decomposition of space and time into separate variables contains an inherent ambiguity on the scale of 1/c. In other words, he rejected Lorentz's "hidden variable" approach, and insisted on treating the ambiguity in the spacetime decomposition as fundamental. This is interesting in part because, when it came to quantum mechanics, Einstein's instinct was to continue trying to find ways of measuring the "hidden variables", and he was never comfortable with the idea that the Heisenberg uncertainty relations express a fundamental ambiguity in the decomposition of conjugate variables on the scale of h. In 1926, Heisenberg responded to Einstein’s skepticism by pointing out that Einstein himself had taken similarly positivistic ideas as the basis of his special theory of relativity, to which Einstein replied "Perhaps I did use such philosophy earlier, and also wrote of it, but it is nonsense all the same." He argued that there are no theory-free observations. The theory first determines what can be observed.
 
 

No comments:

Post a Comment